20 June 2025

Carroll—A contemporary introduction—Introductory Chapter


Noël Carroll
Philosophy of Art: A contemporary introduction
(1999)


[2]


Introduction


What is philosophy?

The word "philosophy" has many different meanings. ... Herein, "philosophy" will generally refer to a certain academic discipline.

... there are many different schools of philosophy, ... [which] often have different aims and emphases. The type of philosophy that we will we will be exploring in this book is often called analytic philosophy. ...

... it is sometimes called "Anglo-American" philosophy, ... a somewhat misleading label ... it is not ... the only form of academic philosophy in the English-speaking world. ...

... "What exactly does this school of philosophy analyse?" Simplifying drastically, we might say that

what analytic philosophy analyses

[3]

are concepts.

That is why it is sometimes also called

conceptual analysis.

...

Concepts, of course, are fundamental to human life.

Concepts organize our practices.

The concept of a person, for example, ... The concept of a number ... the concept of knowledge ...

Without such concepts, the activities in question would not exist.

Ok,
so politicsmorality,number,
indeed knowledge itself,
these practices (a.k.a. activities)
simply would not exist
without the requisite concepts.

How about without the words?

Must we possess the word
in order to possess the concept?

...

A rough and ready way to characterize analytic philosophy is to say that it is concerned with the analysis of

concepts that are key to human practices and activities,

including not only

those of enquiry,

like science, but, as well, of

pragmatic endeavors,

such as governance.

So, both
the practice of enquiry
and its more pragmatic cousins
can be counted on
to generate concepts,
but not
to generate analysis of those concepts.

What if the "practice" just is the "analysis"?
: ^ [

Presumably if pre-analytic concepts not only organize our practices but in fact are what allow practices to exist at all, then those concepts cannot be utterly incoherent; if they were then any practice truly dependent on them for its mere existence wouldn't work; presumably it would just collapse, or indeed would not exist (or would not "work") in the first place.

Indeed, there's a case to be made that our practices mostly do not really work, not unless and until (to provisionally go along with the above discussion) their "concepts" have been sufficiently "analysed."

Of course I'm thinking here, as always, of Becker:

" . . . man seems to have been permitted by natural bounty to live largely in a world of playful fantasy . . . "

(The Birth and Death of Meaning, p. 128)

Etc., etc.

That being as it is, to borrow and repurpose an infamous piece of press conference candor from Mike Tomlin: these practices, in all their presumed-and-presumable incoherence, "have not killed us." So perhaps we often just choose the wrong words with which to denote concepts, but we do not (not quite) as often actually lapse into deadly incoherence. Or perhaps this is exactly what we do most of the time, and deaths are the empirical proof of the fact.

In either/any case, this (death(s)!) is the standard I would prefer we adopt in such matters, most particularly in pragmatic endeavors, such as governance, where there is no excuse remaining for neglecting to adopt it.

And, uh . . . Analysis can miscarry too! And it can be inconclusive or, indeed, irresolvable qua analysis. So eventually, if we really believe in an analysis, we have to try it. (Taleb: "skin in the game.")

So . . . practice is the "culminating science" (A. Bloom). Philosophy (this kind at least) really is not. (And perhaps "analysis" really is not what Bloom had in mind with this remark. TBC . . . )

...

... Philosophy generally seems to be the philosophy of something. But what sort of something?

That something is a practice, like law or religion. ...

Philosophy begins when the people involved in the relevant practices become self-conscious—when they begin to wonder about just what it is that they are doing or just what they are really talking about.

That is,

each one of these practices organizes its field of operation in terms of certain concepts,

which are applied according to certain criteria.

In addition,

each of these practices employs certain recurrent modes of reasoning—

certain ways of connecting concepts which modes are appropriate to the point of achieving the goals of the practice in question.

These concepts and modes of reasoning are what make the practice possible—

they are what, so to speak, constitutes the practice.

And it is such concepts and modes of reasoning that analytic philosophy analyses.

[4]

To be more concrete, consider the case of the law. ...

... Is a law just what some duly appointed assembly decides ... ? Or is a law ... such that it must follow from or at least be consistent with deep principles— ... What arguments can be brought forward on behalf of these different options?

Such questions ... are not idle. ... to allege that a draft law—or, for that matter any law—is illegal—i.e., is against the law—brings us to the very brink of paradox. ...

In addressing [such] questions ... analytic philosophers, among other things, attempt to

identify the criteria that we use to categorize things one way rather than another.

Sometimes this is dismissed as merely

playing with words.

However, when one considers

how very much can ride on questions of categorization,

it seems that analytic philosophers are generally less naive than those who disparage them as "mere logic choppers."

I do think that a real question can be raised about the necessity of concepts to practices.

Concepts seem to have more to do with justifying practices, whether before or after the fact, than they have to do with making practices possible. Recall Becker above. Cynical as it is say it quite so baldly, practices have a way of "working" if we decide that we really want (read: need) them to "work." Material reality does not actually test us nearly as often or as severely as it might; otherwise, if the actual, post-analytic+analytic coherence of our concepts is any true indicator, indeed we'd all be dead.

The necessity for explicit conceptual analysis is more than an artifact of self-consciousness: rather, both the need for analysis and the "self-consciousness" itself are artifacts of (1) pluralism, and (2) record-keeping, and of myriad epiphenomena of these two (at least) "practical" factors. This is all the result, in other words, of invidious comparison, which is usually adequate to reveal the empirical shortcomings of a "practice," though it is no "analysis" unto itself, not even by the relaxed practical definition I suggest above.

Becker:

"what man really fears is not so much extinction, but extinction with insignifcance.

(Escape From Evil, p. 4)

We might add by way of making the implicit explicit: Incoherence is insignificance. Certainly this is so for contemporary intellectuals, doubly so after the fact of "analysis," for which all of us must be responsible no matter how we feel about it.

But again: the concept is not the word. Every fully-developed adult possesses the concept of "incoherence" as it is used here. Becker again has the evidence:

"Cultural illusion is a necessary ideology of self-justification, a heroic dimension that is life itself to the symbolic animal. To lose the security of heroic cultural illusion is to die—that is what "deculturation" of primitives means and what it does."

(The Denial of Death, p. 189)

Invidious comparison may actually be the very most effective way of revealing practical flaws: it strikes at the very heart of what Becker (somewhat awkwardly) labels the "heroic cultural illusion" of culture. And of course it requires nothing so involved or elusive as "analysis," nor does it itself amount to an "analysis." And today even this does insufficient justice to how easily the "practice" of invidious comparison comes to us: under present conditions it is very nearly in the air we breathe. (A truly coherent life "practice" and a truly life-giving "cultural illusion" certainly would not allow that to happen!)

In any event: To ask, simply, whether a practice is or is not serving its ostensible purpose necessarily entails no "analysis" per se. To ask this question and to answer it, this is not even philosophy.

" . . . Make the axe handle longer so that we can reach the highest branches. . . . "

" . . . Ugh lied about the length of his axe, so he's probably lying about its sharpness too. . . . "

It doesn't get any easier than that!

Throughout much of the twentieth century, analytic philosophy has increasingly become

a "second order" form of enquiry.

It is

the philosophy of this or that

the philosophy of physics,
or of economics,
or of art.

Analytic philosophers take as their domain significant forms of human practice, but

unlike the social scientist, the analytic philosopher does not look for recurring patterns of social behavior within said practices.

Instead, the analytic philosopher tries to to clarify the concepts that make activities within the relevant domains possible. Analytic philosophers, in other words, do not attempt to ascertain answers to empirical questions ...

Undoubtedly,

learning how many people obey the law

is crucial for designing social policy. But

discovering what a law is, or attempting to do so,

is an important project too, since if we ignore this question, we will be left wondering whether our practice is intelligible—whether it hangs together, and has any rhyme or reason.

Who wonders about the intelligibility of their own practices? No one, not without some rather severe prompting.

"Everyone has a plan until they get punched in the mouth."

Our "plan" is that our practice is intelligible. We're counting on it. A tap on the shoulder won't dissuade us; we have to get "punched in the mouth" before we really start to wonder.

Why must we "analyse" our own "concepts"? Who threw the punch? Our practices would not collapse without being analysed. That is absurd. We analyze because our "heroic cultural illusions" are now under constant attack from a hundred different directions. In other words, when you live in a pluralistic society (if you do), you simply must analyze your concepts. Nowadays this is mere scheduled maintenance performed on your late-model "cultural illusion."

To whom are our practices truly unintelligible? Certainly not to us ourselves, but perhaps to others who practice differently; and if we, along with these others, are nonetheless mutually integrated into the same elemental (sub-"practical") structures of life, then eventually someone is going to demand that we produce some good reasons for the disjuncture.

Wouldn't you want to hear at least one good reason before signing off on a ritual sacrifice, or even on a certain kind of artwork?

...

[5]

... This is not the only form of philosophy imaginable, but it is a

significant form.

LOL!!

...

... even at this juncture, the idea of clarifying concepts should not be utterly alien to you, since for the last few pages, we have been analysing a concept—namely, the concept of analytic philosophy.

Cute!

...



The analytic philosophy of art

... The purpose of the analytic philosophy of art is to explore

the concepts that make creating and thinking about art possible.

... : the very concept of art itself, ... representation, expression, artistic form, and aesthetics.

Hmm. None of these seem truly necessary for creating art.

They aren't necessary for thinking about art either, but certainly these are concepts that some people who think about art have thought about.

These concepts will be discussed at some length in this book.

; - ]

...

... We have suggested how central the concept of the law is to the practice of jurisprudence. Similarly, the concept of art is fundamental to our artistic practices. Without some sense of

how to classify certain objects and performances

as artworks, the Museum of Modern Art wouldn't know

what to collect,

the National Endowment for the Arts wouldn't know

to whom to give money,

nor would the United States government know

which institutions deserve tax relief

for the preservation

[6]

of our artistic past.

Ok, Boomer!

These latter also are not necessary to the creating of or thinking about art. Try again.

Better yet, these are the canonical examples supporting the larger argument that artists and audiences can quite well do without the sorts of concepts that institutions require. The "practices" of institutions are best evidence yet that institutions themselves have created the concepts.

The mere "practices" of art-making and art-consumption don't even create such concepts, let alone "analyse" them in any way other than the way of practice itself. It's unclear how any practice could depend upon concepts that aren't generated (or not reliably generated) in and by the general run of things.

(Famously, the "practices" of many great artists often enough do not generate very many words to go with any concepts implicated by their practices. If this seems not to be the case anymore, well . . . see my comments to p. 4 above.)

Nor even, without some command of the concept of art, would economists know how to evaluate empirical claims like "Art is a significant component of the financial well-being of New York City."

Perhaps I, in my pre-analytic state vis-a-vis financial well-being, only think I know how to evaluate this particular empirical claim . . . but if this is the sort of "claim" that analysis would underwrite, then I say: hold the analysis, please.

But far more important than the preceding

"official" uses

of the concept of art is the role the concept plays in

our personal, ongning commerce with artworks,

since how we respond to an object—interpretively, appreciatively, emotively, and evaluatively—depends decisively upon

whether or not we categorize it as an artwork.

Suppose we come across a living, breathing couple seated at opposite sides of a wooden table, staring intently at each other. Ordinarily we might pay no attention to them at all, ... But if we categorise the situation as an artwork—as the performance piece Night Crossing by Marina Abramovic and Ulay—our response will be altogether different.

We will

shamelessly scrutinize

the scene carefully,

attempt to interpret it, ...

try to situate it

in the history of art, ... We will

contemplate what it expresses and what feelings it arouses in us,

and may

evaluate it

possibly

commending it for drawing our attention to neglected realms of experience,

... Or maybe we will

criticize it

for being boring or hackneyed. But in any event, it is clear that

once we categorize the situation as an artwork, our response will differ radically

from the way in which we regard comparable seated couples

in "real" life.

... we do not think of [surgical procedures] as alternatives to a night at the opera. But when such procedures are incorporated in a performance piece ... , we see it in a different light. We

note the interesting color arrangement

of the surgeons uniforms and we

ask about the meaning

of Orlan's self-elected decision to go under the knife—
...
That is, we

react to the event completely differently

from how we would,
had we happened upon an ordinary gall-bladder operation.
The

attempt to interpret the meaning of your typical gall bladder operation

is out of place,
but the

attempt to interpret an artwork is usually appropriate.

Yet interpretation

here hinges

on whether or not we

classify the item in question as an artwork

on whether we

correctly apply the concept of art to it.

Thus, clarifying our concept of art is not merely a matter of dry, academic book-keeping. ...

[7]

... In order to play the game, we need a handle on the concept of art. And it is the task of the analytic philosophy of art to make sure that that handle is a sturdy one ...

This is slightly perverse.

There was analytic philosophy
before there were performance pieces.

In any case,

if you don't need analytic philosophy to recognize your typical gall bladder operation

why should you need it in order to categorize any other situation?

Do we typically have to analyze situations
just to know what kind of situations they are?

Or do we only have to do this in art but not in life?

...

Analysing concepts

... How do you go about analysing concepts? ...

... there is substantial debate about what concepts are and how to analyse them. However, there is one very standard approach ... We can call this standard approach the method of necessary and sufficient conditions. It proceeds by

breaking concepts down into their necessary and sufficient conditions for application.

Although this method is controversial, we shall presume its practicability for most of this text, if only because

it is a powerful tool for organizing and guiding research,

even if ultimately

it rests on certain questionable assumptions.

The standard approach takes

concepts to be categories.

Applying a certain concept to an object is a matter of

classifying it as a member of the relevant category.

... Analysing a concept is a matter of breaking it down into its component parts, where

the component parts are its conditions for application.

Think of the concept bachelor. ... We can break down or analyse the concept of bachelor into two component parts—manhood and unmarriedness. ...

[8]

... Individually, each of these conditions is necessary for anything to count as a bachelor, and together (conjointly) they are sufficient (just enough) to categorize a candidate as a bachelor. ...

... you want to know

(1) the feature or features of the kind in question that every proper member of the category possesses;
and
(2) you want to know what feature or features differentiate members of the relevant kind or category from members of other kinds.

For example, if you want to know what a bachelor is—

how to apply the concept bachelor

then you want to know

what all bachelors have in common

and also

what sets bachelors apart

...

... you want know what feature or features are necessarily possessed by all the proper members of the category, such that absence of the feature in question precludes membership in the category ...

...
"x is a necessary condition for y"
means that
something can be a y only if it is an x.

[e.g.]
Someone can be a princess
only if she is a woman.

We cannot, however, say that if y is a woman, then she is a princess. ... Womanhood is not a sufficient condition for princesshood; ... A likely candidate is that y be of royal lineage, ...

[9]

...

...

The locution "if and only if" signals that this analysis is proposing necessary conditions (the "only if" conditions) and sufficient conditions (the "if" conditions) for princesshood. ...

This kind of analysis is often called a

real

or an

essential

definition. ... essential ... because it attempts to get at the essential features of the concept—its necessary and sufficient conditions of application. ... real ... because unlike so many dictionary definitions it does not simply track

how people commonly use the concept,

but allegedly discovers

the real conditions of application

of the concept.

...

... this approach to the way in which we go about applying concepts is controversial ... alternative views will be explored in the last chapter of this book.

Yet until the last chapter, we will be employing this approach to analysing concepts pretty much without worrying about its adequacy. This might strike you as strange and even irresponsible, if the approach is really disputed.

So far my misgivings are about the proposed applications of the approach. Why not stare into the abyss from time to time? Why not be willing to examine one's own "practices"? But you were alive and kicking before you ever thought to do that, or before someone else told you that you had better cop a look or else risk living an "incoherent" life.

But let me make two remarks on behalf of this procedure.

[10]

One objection

to the essential definition approach is that

many of our concepts are applied without resort to necessary and sufficient conditions.

Arguably, many of our concepts do not have necessary and/or suffficient conditions of application. There is no reason to

presume

that the concepts that we explore by means of this method will turn out

to be analysable

in terms of necessary and/or sufficient conditions.
That is a fair observation.
However, since

we won't know know whether a given concept is congenial to this mode of analysis until we've tried it,

we have no grounds for dismissing this approach from the get-go.

Second, even if the method of definition does not turn out to be the best way of understanding how to go about applying concepts, the method still has

immense heuristic value.

By "heuristic value,"
we mean that
the method of definition,
even when it fails,
can

assist us in making discoveries.

The method

alerts us systematically

to

the richness and complexity

of the phenomenon that confronts us.

Yes.

...

... [e.g.] there is a great deal of self expressive behavior in everyday life—like the tantrums of a hungry infant—that are not artworks, ... But ... we not only learn that the self-expression theory is false, but that subsequent theorizing must be

alert to the distinction

between self expression that is art versus that which is not.
The method of definition, then, is

conducive to an awareness of "joints" in the data

that any future attempts at dissection must respect.

...

[11]

Some peculiarities of philosophical research

... if your background is in the empirical sciences. ... you might presume that [analytic philosophy as presented above] is some kind of social science. ...

[But]

Philosophy is not social science.

...

Consider the empirical claim: there is more art in Paris than there is in Spokane. The sociologist assesses this claim by counting ... But ... this ... rests on an assumption—namely that the sociologist

knows how to apply the concept

of art. ... But determining the correct application of our classificatory categories ... is not an empirical question.

... It involves clarifying the classificatory categories that we will use in organizing empirical observations, ... reflecting upon how we apply the concept of art, testing it intellectually against what we believe to be established applications of the concept, ...

... we cannot discover the concept of art by

[12]

polling. ... Because many people have false beliefs shout what is art. ... A social scientist relying on a poll ... would miscount all the artworks in Paris in 1930; ...

The philosopher is not interested in establishing

what most people believe is art,

though this is a worthwhile thing to know, ... the philosopher wants know how to apply the concept of art

correctly or justifiably.

...

...

Another way to suggest the difference ... the philosopher is preoccupied with

what must be the case,

whereas the social scientist is more concerned with

what probably is the case
most of the time.

Umm . . . BURN?? 🔥🔥🔥

The philosopher

tries

to identify ... a feature of a work that it must necessarily possess in order to count as artwork. A social scientist

is happy

to discover what most people in a given society are likely to consider art. ...

... armchair speculation is not what is encouraged in the empirical sciences; ... This is why students sometimes find analytic philosophy so exasperating. ...

[13]

...

But, ...

not all such questions can be resolved empirically;

...

...

...

...

The structure of this book

...

[14]

...

... in each of these chapters it is also noted
that
even if the concepts people have used to define all and only art ... fail to supply necessary and sufficient conditions for all and only art, these concepts— ... are still applicable to many works of art,
and,
therefore,
still warrant philosophical analysis ... Thus, in Part II of each of the first four chapters, analyses of representation, expression, form and the notion of aesthetics are explored.

...

... The problem with with commendatory theories of art

Here and henceforth Our Man seems maniacally intent upon avoiding Weitz's term, "honorific", which is . . . just better than commendatory in every imaginable way.

i.e. Honorific definitions are,

"proposed redefinitions in terms of some chosen conditions for applying the concept of art, and not true or false reports on the essential properties of art"

(Weitz, p. 146)

Can we just follow the concise Weitz and call them

"honorific definitions"

?

(This isn't . . . an IP issue, is it? Because it would be quite the tragedy-and-farce for an analytic philosopher in the vein sketched above to find that they truly own their work, and that they may build on the work of others but they definitely do not own it.)

(Thanks to the wonders of 1990s technology, I can confirm, here in 2025, that the word "honorific" indeed does not appear in the book. Hmm . . . )

[the problem] is that [honorific definitions] , in effect, only count as artworks those that are good— ... [but] there is such a thing as bad art— ...

... By the fifth chapter of the book, we will have encountered so many failed definitions of art that it will be time to ask whether there might be some deep philosophical problem with attempting to analyse the concept of art in terms of sets of necessary and/or sufficient conditions.

...

[15]

...

...

...

In Part III of Chapter 5, historical narration is advanced as the primary way in which we sort artworks from other things. This is neither a matter of definitions nor of what the Neo-Wittgensteinians call family resemblances. In fact, this solution to the unavoidable philosophical question of the way in which we identify artworks is

a pet idea of the present author.

...

The aims of this book

... A great many of the theories reviewed in this book are what might be called canonical. They are theories that anyone who cares for art should know about. ...

... familiarity with these theories and the criticisms they have attracted is part of the indispensable operating knowledge that one needs in order to follow and join in contemporary

[16]

discussions in the philosophy of art. ...

... though a great deal of the technique displayed in this book is critical, the aim of the book is to enable you to construct your own approaches ... There is still a great deal of

room for improvement

in the philosophy of art, and inevitably it is up to your generation ...

Of all of these stated aims, I'd say that the book really makes good on this one. Anyone with half a brain will come away agreeing that there is ample room for improvement.

... Many of the skills that this book exercises involve

ways of showing that theories and viewpoints mistaken.

... this may leave the depressing impression that the philosophy of art is little more than destructive, ...

... [But] it is through criticism that knowledge and understanding are advanced. ... Taking note of what one theory has overlooked or neglected makes you aware of what should not be overlooked or neglected the next time around. ...

...

[17]

...

... Philosophical theories often

evolve dialectically.

Each step forward involves the rejection of parts of previous philosophies and the assimilation of other parts. In either case,

criticism is the engine

that drives philosophical evolution and should not be misconstrued as

mean-spiritedness.

...

Welcome to the dialectic.

Welcome to my criticism, sir.





16 May 2025

Ted Cohen—The Possibility of Art


Philosophy Looks at the Arts
ed. Joseph Margolis
(Third Edition, 1987)


[186]

10. The Possibility of Art:
Remarks on a Proposal by Dickie

TED COHEN
[orig. 1973]



... Like much of Dickie's best work, this essay ["Defining Art"] is brief, direct, and convincing ... This time, however, I think he has tried to make things more simple and ingenuous than they can be.

The definition Dickie presents ...

A work of art in the descriptive sense is (1) an artifact (2) upon which some society or some sub-group of a society has conferred the status of candidate for appreciation .

... it may be helpful to note three special features of Dickie's thesis.


03 May 2025

JACK GLICKMAN—Creativity in the Arts


Philosophy Looks at the Arts
ed. Joseph Margolis
(Third Edition, 1987)




[168]

9. Creativity in the Arts

JACK GLICKMAN
[orig. 1976]

I

What is it to be creative?

The answer usually given
is that there is a "creative process,"
and most writers on creativity have taken their task
to be a description of ... activity ...

... I will argue that that is the wrong way to go about characterizing creativity,
that one must attend to the artistic product rather than to the process.

Well . . . speaking again as a twice-over Music Major, immediately I see one obvious candidate explanation for why most writers on creativity would emphasize the process rather than the product: because they are teachers of prospective practitioners, not of prospective scholars; their prospective-practitioner students cannot learn the process directly from inspection of the product.

27 March 2025

The Dixieland Nightmare

"Keep it simple."

But there isn't a simple solution to the VI7(♭13 ) chord, i.e. in Bourbon Street Parade, Sheik of Araby, Whispering, Rock-a-Bye Your Baby, Wait 'Till the Sun Shines Nellie, and who knows how many other tradjazz warhorses.

This chord has been the bane of my existence for as long as my ears have been awake to it. In my nightmares and often in real life too, it goes down something like this:

If the melody player knows one note of the actual melody, it's probably the ♭13, because that's the highest, tensest note in the chart. So the cherry is always on top, no matter what kind of sundae is on the menu that day.

The bass player has been scolded to "keep it simple," and so given any G chord, the options are G and D. That's it. The language used to describe bass players who play notes other than G and D is even less flattering than the old joke about players who can do only this. So, "simply" put, this is a dominant chord, shit runs downhill, and payday is on Friday.

The chord player, meanwhile, has been playing these songs for decades and hasn't looked at a chart in years, but they know that G-B-Eb forms an augmented triad, hence that we are dealing here with a Black Sheep offshoot of the Augmented family, and that the remaining members of this clan are A-C#-F. And although the chord player is too tasteful to overdo it, planing is definitely a thing, and so planing there will be.

In other words, if everyone narrowly assimilates to their role, eventually there will be at least one C#-D-Eb pile-up, and probably more than one. This is especially likely in Sheik where the chord just sits there for two whole bars at medium tempo. If there are more than a couple of solos then there almost certainly will be a D-Eb-E pile-up too. This is the tradjazz version of thematic development.

I'm being extremely pedantic and a bit viscious here, but I promise there is a point to it.

The point is: the bass and chord players can't treat this chord as either a straight dominant OR augmented chord, because IT IS NEITHER of those things. By the most obvious analysis it is only one note away, but that analysis is so misleading as to deserve to be labeled actually "wrong." The functional diatonic weighting and countour of this chord are unique in tonal music. Hence there also is no point in everyone simply agreeing to treat it as straight dominant or augmented. That doesn't fit any of these melodies anyway, as parties to any such agreement will be quickly and viscerally reminded; but even if it did there would be much lost and nothing gained this way.

Technically, in the case of the above-named tunes, I believe this chordscale is best analyzed as "fifth mode of harmonic (or melodic) minor";

i.e. G7(♭13 ) = C harmonic (or melodic) minor starting on G;

but that is far too verbose to be useful, especially for tradjazzers who would rather live with the clams than bring this kind of talk into the band. So, I propose we label it the "Dixieland Nightmare" chord, in honor of an offhand remark that was once made to me by a bandleader.

In high school and college this chord used to drive me nuts as a listener, but now it drives me nuts as a bass (function) player. 

Staying with G7 as the working example:

If the melody shuttles between E-flat and D, then both of those notes are out; C is outest-of-out, as always; and there is an unresolved ambiguity even in what I consider to be the "correct" reference analysis of the chord, namely: are we using harmonic or melodic minor? i.e. Is it A or A-flat? So even there, one of the most obvious "simple"-but-hip solutions, the G-A-B walkup, comes with the same risk of a pile-up.

And so . . . buckle up, hornheads! The F is a really attractive option. The F is both minimally consonant AND minimally risky. So, we can walk DOWN, G to F; we can even do one full bar of each if we must; and this is a very elegant solution! Most days it seems to me like the ONLY elegant solution. The problem (for others, not for me) is that this lands us on the third of the impending C7 chord. Unless you're dealing with exceptionally hardheaded necrophile purists, this is also quite elegant against the resolution to D in the melody. There are two problems, though. (1) Those necrophiles ARE out there; and (2) generally putting the third on the bottom in this style IS actually pretty destabilizing, and people get annoyed with it when it happens all the time; that is why bass players are so often admonished to "keep it simple" even where doing so creates clams rather than preventing them.

So, as nice as this line is, you can't play it every time. Probably you can only play it once per song, and there are likely to be more choruses than there are unique workable solutions. You can probably get away with the G-A-B walkup, one way or another. I often find myself ghosting the dangerous note in those once-bitten-twice-shy moments. And again, "keeping it moving" IS a viable alternative to "keeping it simple": you can fill-ghost with G-A-B♭-B such that the NCTs really are placed and articulated like NCTs and the anchors like anchors; and this (I really REALLY mean this) usually leads to better results and happier sidespersons as compared with letting some necrophile talk you into "keeping it simple."

"You played a Bb under a G7 chord!" Sure did. If you want to fight about it, fight with Messrs. J.S. Bach and P. Chambers, for starters. Just realize that you're fighting the music that came BEFORE tradjazz at least as much as the music that came after it; you're not just damming the backwash, you're damming the headwaters too. That is really Somethin' Else!

22 March 2025

ARTHUR DANTO—The Artworld


Philosophy Looks at the Arts
ed. Joseph Margolis
(Third Edition, 1987)




[153]

The Artworld

ARTHUR DANTO

[orig. 1964]



Hamlet:
Do you see nothing there?
The Queen:
Nothing at all; yet all that is I see.
Shakespeare: Hamlet, Act 3, Scene 4


Hamlet and Socrates,
though in praise and depreciation respectively,
spoke of art
as a mirror held up to nature.

As with many disagreements in attitude,
this one has a factual basis.

Socrates saw mirrors as but reflecting what we can already see; ...
idle accurate duplications ...
of no cognitive benefit whatever.

Hamlet,
more acutely,
recognized a remarkable feature of reflecting surfaces,
namely that
they show us what we could not otherwise perceive—
our own face and form—

and so art,
insofar as it is mirrorlike,
reveals us to ourselves,
and is, even by Socratic criteria,
of some cognitive utility
after all.

Sure, why not?

Just make doubly sure you are actually looking at a reflection and not a projection.

21 March 2025

[sc]airquotes (ix)—in praise of dick-thinking


Herb Goldberg
The Hazards of Being Male
(1976)


[22]

3. The Wisdom
Of The Penis

...

The essence and ultimate joy of male sexuality lies in the experience of total arousal, the moment when nothing in the world exists except the woman beside him, ... —desire at such a peak that no fantasies could possibly intrude ...

... it is a state most men have experienced at some time in their lives before they allowed their sexual spontaneity to be mired in the intellectualizations about "sexuality," derailed by abstractions about "meaningful relationships" and "sharing," alienated from their own experience by a destructive emphasis on techniques, and numbed by scientific teachings about the physiology of the woman and himself. That, to my mind, is the essence of much of the so-called new sexual enlightenment—the "progress" and the problem.

While women's sexuality has been misunderstood and they've been confused and degrated [sic] by psychoanalytic interpretations ... men, I believe, have been seriously and negatively affected by such labels as "latent homosexuality," "fear of intimacy," "mother fixation," "repressed hostility toward

[23]

women," "fear of failure," ...

Undoubtedly these all contain a basis in truth, but instead of facilitating his growth, the major impact of these concepts and terms have been to propel the male into greater self-consciousness, guilt, and self-accusatory reactions. Belief in these ideas often causes him to distrust his own unique sexual responses.

The beginning of a new male consciousness in the area of sexuality will first require, along with being fully aware of his feelings, a different way of interpreting his responses. ...

... It is true that a boy is given more exploratory privileges and has traditionally been allowed a wider latitude in terms of sexual indulgence. However, cultural evaluations of his sexual behavior have been far more harsh.

Impotence

... In our culture the subject has become an almost maniacal preoccupation.

[24]

... While lip-service is paid to the fact that impotence is a two-way problem, it is the male who is in the majority at the sex therapy clinics. The image of the female's role in male impotence is still largely one of helper—a sometimes supportive, sometimes resentful spectator waiting for him to overcome his problem.

...



The psychoanalytic and psychiatric approach to impotence, which involves tracing back and exploring early experiences and traumas, has a basis in reality but is a little like treating

[25]

food poisoning by exploring early eating habits. It neglects the fact that the real cause may be in the present, with the body appropriately responding to something that is seeks to avoid.

... The vast majority of men are of course capable of becoming erect under certain conditions and with certain women. So-called impotence is almost always a pair-specific phenomenon, that may be making a powerful statement about the man's feelings about the relationship toward the particular woman he is in bed with. Ironic as it may seem, most men, would rather feel they have a medical problem than say very simply to their intimate, "I don't want to make love to you." In other words, acknowledging impotence and claiming, "I've got a problem," is easier than expressing the feeling, "I'm not turned on by you." Therefore, instead of seeing himself as impotent, I would encourage him to say "I don't want to have sex with you." I would have him translate "premature ejaculation" into, "I want to get this over with as fast as possible." I would encourage him to explore and understand his negative responses to the particular woman or situation rather than assume the burden and then try to overcome the "symptom."

My clinical experience indicates that the man who diagnoses himself as impotent is often experiencing something within his relationship or about his partner that is killing his desire. However, the feeling message is only being telegraphed by his body response and is not being recognized in his conscious brain.

A colleague of mine is treating a forty-one-year-old man who became impotent after he lost his job. The patient previously was informed by one well-meaning doctor and had also read in several magazine articles that his inability to achieve erection had something to do with the fact that he associated his job with his masculinity ... An in-depth interview with his wife revealed that she was secretly deeply resentful about his unemployment and blamed

[26]

him for his lack of foresight. Out of guilt, however, she never told him, but she did say to the therapist, "He knew it was bound to happen and he could have done something about it in time, if he had really wanted to." The man's penis was perceiving her unspoken anger and her attitude of rejection toward him and was refusing to "make love" in the face of her anger and rage.

...

A different form of the wisdom of the penis is illustrated by the responses of a twenty-six-year-old recently married engineer. ... The twenty-nine-year-old wife had had two years of psychology courses and had convinced him that he was really angry toward women because of the way his mother had treated him. ... That sounded plausible to him and he came to therapy wanting to be "cured." Several private sessions with his wife, however, brought to light the fact that she had married him primarily because she was approaching thirty and was concerned that she'd never get married. She revealed that she had never been attracted to him physically and had been faking her sexual excitement right from the beginning. ... His penis was aware of her basic lack of true involvement with him. ...

[27]

...

An associate of mine told me of a patient who had recently gone to bed with the wife of a friend of his and found himself impotent. As he explored his reaction he realized that she probably was only using him to precipitate an end to her own faltering marriage. His body sensed this and wisely kept him out of a potentially explosive and dangerous relationship.

In another instance, a forty-two-year-old man became completely impotent with his wife of seventeen years. However, he was extremely potent during occasional visits to prostitutes. When I first spoke to him he was in an extreme anxiety state regarding his inability to perform sexually. He wanted to be "cured" as quickly as possible. ...

As we spoke at greater length however, it readily became apparent that internally he had been experiencing rage toward his wife for many years. ...

He acknowledged that he felt smothered and engulfed by his wife whom he felt resented him and tried to block his every autonomous move. He had been unable to assert himself with her. Instead he had given up his own activities— ... He simply went to work and came home.

While consciously he rationalized his wife's demands and stated that he felt she was justified in her expectations and requests to have him at home with the children, his penis registered his innermost feelings. It was protesting the annihilation of his real self. It was his "truth teller" and it said that he did not really want closeness and physical intimacy with a woman he felt was destroying him.

There are other examples, some so transparent that they are amusing. For example, an obviously hostile woman who was always putting down men, recently asked me if I could confirm her experience that "just about all men today have impotency problems." Clearly, she was not aware of the impact her

[28]

hostility toward men had on her lovers. She apparently believed that erections automatically appear under all conditions. Her underlying assumption was that men have no emotional reactions when it comes to sex, and that a "normal" man will automatically have an erection when there is a naked, willing woman.

Men are not impotent today. They only are impotent with some women under some conditions and their non-responsive reactions reflect important truths that they must learn to trust and understand.

... Certain kinds of contemporary conditioning techniques and "helpful" and "supportive" advice ... would have done these men great disservice. Their basic distrust of the wisdom of their body responses would only have been reinforced.

... I don't believe that an erection, no matter how achieved, is a good thing simply because it reduces a man's anxiety for the moment. I feel that this attitude robs him of the necessity of owning up to his real feelings about his partner or the relationship in which he's involved. The man who gets his erections by cheating on himself through fantasizing sex with other women, arousing himself with pornography, or using various and sundry mechanical devices is demonstrating disrespect for himself and rejection of his real emotions.

... The penis is not a piece of plumbing that functions capriciously. It is an expression of the total self. In these days of over-intellectualization it is perhaps the only remaining sensitive and revealing barometer of the male's true sexual feelings.




Arthur Danto
Analytical Philosophy of Action
(1973)


[116]

5

GIFTS

i

'We are not able to move all the organs of the body with like authority',
Hume observes,
'though we cannot assign any reason besides experience, for so remarkable a difference between one and the other.'

'As we are now',
wrote St Augustine,
'not only do our articulate members obey the will — our hands or feet or fingers — but even those that are moved only by small sinews and tendons we contract and turn as we list, as you may see in the voluntary motions of the mouth and face . . . and the lungs do serve a man's will entirely, like a pair of smith's or organist's bellows.'

Like Hume,
Augustine supposed it merely contingent that our 'authority' should be circumscribed as we find it to be,
for there are men capable of doing odd things: 'We see some men's natures far different from others, acting those things strangely in their bodies which others neither do nor hardly will believe.'

So
we could have been framed
with our authority differently seated:
'God could easily have made us with all our members subjected to the will',
he writes,

adding the possibility
which obviously haunted him as a man,
as we might recall from the Confessions,

'even those which now are moved by lust'.

I italicize the word 'now', which occurs twice in this passage. For it was Augustine's curious view that Adam, in paradise, indeed was so framed that he could perform what I have termed basic actions with his sexual organ, and hence achieve the sexual act immune from the contaminations of sin.

It is thus not sex but lust which is the root of sin, and hence the domination by the flesh of us rather than the domination by us over our bodies, which is the fallen state. Paradise accordingly is a condition we may get some glimpses of from our present powers of direct action, executing intentions without the concomitant torment of desire.



I am not at all certain that
it is a merely contingent matter
that voluntary erection
lies outside the boundaries of direct action.

For curiously enough,
a man who were able to erect at will
might in fact be impotent in the received sense,
which is an incapacity for genuine

[117]

sexual response;

where response implies
precisely the absence of
that order of control
Augustine supposes our first parent
to have exemplified.

A man who had direct control, or who was obliged to exercise direct control, would be a man without feeling, erection being the common expression of male sexual feeling.

And it is in some measure a logical truth that if erection were an action it would not be an expression, and the entire meaning of sexuality would be altered were tumescence something over which we had 'authority'.

Hence feeling,
or lust, if you will,
is not so contingently related to erection
as Augustine's argument implies.

But
perhaps it is his claim that there would in fact have been no sexuality in paradise:
a wry conjecture in the light of post-Freudian sexual romanticism.